International Relations and Security Network (ISN) - Thucydides, or Plato?
COMMENT: This is a recommendation for a useful website and newsletter service will provide timely and critical information about the state of international politics and relationships.
International Relations and Security Network (ISN) - Managing information, sharing knowledge.
www.isn.ethz.ch
The ISN is a service of the Center for Security Studies (CSS) at the ETH Zurich (Swiss Federal Institute of Technology Zurich).
NOTE: This month in their blog the author goes all the way to ancient Greece and the Pelopponesian War nearly 2,500 years ago. International politcs between nation states haven't really changed at all - some new technology, bigger scale, same issues,....those with power rule, those without follow or are ruled.
Reference - accessed on 13 Oct 2011:
http://isnblog.ethz.ch/international-relations/thucydides-or-plato
International Relations and Security Network (ISN) - Managing information, sharing knowledge.
www.isn.ethz.ch
The ISN is a service of the Center for Security Studies (CSS) at the ETH Zurich (Swiss Federal Institute of Technology Zurich).
NOTE: This month in their blog the author goes all the way to ancient Greece and the Pelopponesian War nearly 2,500 years ago. International politcs between nation states haven't really changed at all - some new technology, bigger scale, same issues,....those with power rule, those without follow or are ruled.
Reference - accessed on 13 Oct 2011:
http://isnblog.ethz.ch/international-relations/thucydides-or-plato
Thucydides, or Plato?
Filed under: International Relations by William Rooke on Thursday, 13 October 2011 | No Comments
Tags: IR Theory, plato, Realism, thucydides
Tags: IR Theory, plato, Realism, thucydides
Most university courses in International Relations, if they have a theoretical or historical bent at all, tend to consider Thucydides to have been the first important contributor to ‘international’ thought. Though Herodotus is the “father of history” and it was Socrates that first brought philosophy down from the heavens and into the agora, Thucydides is usually considered the first to have dealt explicitly with the nature of the relations among and between political communities in what begins to resemble a theoretical manner.
Thucydides’ most important work is the History of the Peloponnesian War, which recounts the 27-year struggle in the 5th century BC between the Greek city-states of Athens and Sparta. Perhaps the most famous element of the book is its account of the war’s ultimate causes, which Thucydides describes as the “growth in power of Athens, and the alarm which this inspired in Sparta.” What is immediately clear to students of international relations is the consonance of this explanation with what Kenneth Waltz would call “third image” theory. According to Thucydides, it was neither the malign nature of any of the human beings involved, nor the authoritarian character of the Spartan regime, but changes in the relative distribution of power in the ancient Greek international-political system (if you will), that caused the war. One begins to see why so many courses start here.
As any classicist will tell you, of course, Thucydides is more complicated than this. But it is true that the most dramatic passages in the History lend themselves quite easily to realist hagiography. Consider the so-called ‘ Melian dialogue‘ — perhaps the book’s second most famous passage – in which the Athenian envoy to Melos, a much less powerful city-state, informs his counterpart: “you know as well as we do that right, as the world goes, is only in question between equals in power, while the strong do what they will and the weak suffer what they must.”
This is one of earliest arguments for the primacy of power and security in international relations. Without question, it echoes one of the most important passages in political thought of any kind, the famous intrusion in Book 1 of Plato’s Republic by the sophist Thrasymachus, advancing the immoralist thesis that “justice is [merely] the advantage of the stronger”, and that “injustice, if it is on a large enough scale, is stronger, freer, and more masterly than justice’”. Ultimately, it is this challenge that motivates what takes up the vast majority of the Republic: the attempt by Socrates and his friends to construct an ideally just “city in speech.”
Largely on the merit of that attempt, Plato is widely considered the first important political thinker in the Western tradition. Many, however, are unaware of his ‘international’ thought, where he actually emerges as a rival to Thucydides. In the first Book of the Republic, Socrates begins to talk about matters of justice among city states, but is interrupted by Thrasymachus. The topic of war then re-surfaces in Books 2 and 3, where Socrates identifies its origins in the desire for “the customary luxuries” and appoints a warrior class of guardians whose profession is “the art of war.” But Socrates in the Republic never clarifies what this ‘art of war’ means in practice and how it serves justice (as it must, as part of the ideally just city). But, for that, there are the other dialogues: Timaeus, The Laws, and the mostly lost Critias.
In these three dialogues, Plato turns directly to what looks to us like international relations. In Timaeus and Critias (which are set on the day after the conversations that appear in the Republic), Socrates expresses his dissatisfaction with the ideally just city that he and his friends constructed, complaining that it “is like seeing beautiful creatures at rest, and ignores the activities for which they appear to be formed.” As the discussion then immediately takes up the mythological war between an ideal-typical ur-Athens and Atlantis, it seems likely that, for Plato, international relations are precisely these activities for which city-states “appear to be formed.”* One prominent scholar has even argued that the theme of Critias (of which only fragments survive) was, in fact, “a theoretical discussion of international relations.” In any event, these arguments put the ‘international’ question very near the center of Plato’s project.
Though we will probably never know what the fragmentary Critias contained, Plato can still be as foundational a figure for international thought as Thucydides. In my opinion, this matters. While Thucydides is usually conscripted into the service of one school of thought in particular, Plato provides a much more pluralist point of departure. As 2000 years of classical philology will attest, conclusions about what Plato actually believed or recommended are often elusive, but the full gamut of contemporary approaches to international relations — and then some — are recognizable in his writings.
In Book 1 of The Laws, for example, realists will find an ally in Cleinias, who argues that “what most men call peace is really only a fiction, and that in cold fact states are by nature fighting an undeclared war against every other state.” Book 3, which is a speculative history of the development of ‘international’ norms among the Greek (but not other) city-states, is useful fodder for English School theorists, constructivists, and cultural realists alike. And this is only the tip of the iceberg.
Though starting with Plato instead of Thucydides may seem a petty academic matter, we should not underestimate the power of the idea — to which starting with Thucydides lends credence – that 2500 hundred years ago in radically different circumstances, the first ‘international’ thinker was already a realist, or a liberal, or whatever else. Plato is the perfect antidote to this.
*This contradicts the views of many classicists — including Hannah Arendt and Leo Strauss — who believed that the individual city state was the highest concern of ancient Greek political thought.
Reference - accessed on 13 Oct 2011:
http://isnblog.ethz.ch/international-relations/thucydides-or-plato
International Relations and Security Network (ISN) - Managing information, sharing knowledge.
www.isn.ethz.ch
The ISN is a service of the Center for Security Studies (CSS) at the ETH Zurich (Swiss Federal Institute of Technology Zurich).
Thucydides’ most important work is the History of the Peloponnesian War, which recounts the 27-year struggle in the 5th century BC between the Greek city-states of Athens and Sparta. Perhaps the most famous element of the book is its account of the war’s ultimate causes, which Thucydides describes as the “growth in power of Athens, and the alarm which this inspired in Sparta.” What is immediately clear to students of international relations is the consonance of this explanation with what Kenneth Waltz would call “third image” theory. According to Thucydides, it was neither the malign nature of any of the human beings involved, nor the authoritarian character of the Spartan regime, but changes in the relative distribution of power in the ancient Greek international-political system (if you will), that caused the war. One begins to see why so many courses start here.
This is one of earliest arguments for the primacy of power and security in international relations. Without question, it echoes one of the most important passages in political thought of any kind, the famous intrusion in Book 1 of Plato’s Republic by the sophist Thrasymachus, advancing the immoralist thesis that “justice is [merely] the advantage of the stronger”, and that “injustice, if it is on a large enough scale, is stronger, freer, and more masterly than justice’”. Ultimately, it is this challenge that motivates what takes up the vast majority of the Republic: the attempt by Socrates and his friends to construct an ideally just “city in speech.”
Largely on the merit of that attempt, Plato is widely considered the first important political thinker in the Western tradition. Many, however, are unaware of his ‘international’ thought, where he actually emerges as a rival to Thucydides. In the first Book of the Republic, Socrates begins to talk about matters of justice among city states, but is interrupted by Thrasymachus. The topic of war then re-surfaces in Books 2 and 3, where Socrates identifies its origins in the desire for “the customary luxuries” and appoints a warrior class of guardians whose profession is “the art of war.” But Socrates in the Republic never clarifies what this ‘art of war’ means in practice and how it serves justice (as it must, as part of the ideally just city). But, for that, there are the other dialogues: Timaeus, The Laws, and the mostly lost Critias.
In these three dialogues, Plato turns directly to what looks to us like international relations. In Timaeus and Critias (which are set on the day after the conversations that appear in the Republic), Socrates expresses his dissatisfaction with the ideally just city that he and his friends constructed, complaining that it “is like seeing beautiful creatures at rest, and ignores the activities for which they appear to be formed.” As the discussion then immediately takes up the mythological war between an ideal-typical ur-Athens and Atlantis, it seems likely that, for Plato, international relations are precisely these activities for which city-states “appear to be formed.”* One prominent scholar has even argued that the theme of Critias (of which only fragments survive) was, in fact, “a theoretical discussion of international relations.” In any event, these arguments put the ‘international’ question very near the center of Plato’s project.
Though we will probably never know what the fragmentary Critias contained, Plato can still be as foundational a figure for international thought as Thucydides. In my opinion, this matters. While Thucydides is usually conscripted into the service of one school of thought in particular, Plato provides a much more pluralist point of departure. As 2000 years of classical philology will attest, conclusions about what Plato actually believed or recommended are often elusive, but the full gamut of contemporary approaches to international relations — and then some — are recognizable in his writings.
In Book 1 of The Laws, for example, realists will find an ally in Cleinias, who argues that “what most men call peace is really only a fiction, and that in cold fact states are by nature fighting an undeclared war against every other state.” Book 3, which is a speculative history of the development of ‘international’ norms among the Greek (but not other) city-states, is useful fodder for English School theorists, constructivists, and cultural realists alike. And this is only the tip of the iceberg.
Though starting with Plato instead of Thucydides may seem a petty academic matter, we should not underestimate the power of the idea — to which starting with Thucydides lends credence – that 2500 hundred years ago in radically different circumstances, the first ‘international’ thinker was already a realist, or a liberal, or whatever else. Plato is the perfect antidote to this.
*This contradicts the views of many classicists — including Hannah Arendt and Leo Strauss — who believed that the individual city state was the highest concern of ancient Greek political thought.
Reference - accessed on 13 Oct 2011:
http://isnblog.ethz.ch/international-relations/thucydides-or-plato
International Relations and Security Network (ISN) - Managing information, sharing knowledge.
www.isn.ethz.ch
The ISN is a service of the Center for Security Studies (CSS) at the ETH Zurich (Swiss Federal Institute of Technology Zurich).
- Get link
- X
- Other Apps
Labels:
common sense
defense
government
homeland
politicians
principles
public
security
survival
sustainability
United Nations
Comments
Post a Comment